====== Affirming a disjunct ====== A [[logic:formal_fallacies:index|formal fallacy]] in which a positive (affirmative) result for one alternative of an [[glossary:adjunction|adjunct]] statement is (mis-)interpreted to imply a negative result for the other option The following is an example of an affirmation of a disjunction: > It will rain //or// snow today. > It is raining. > Therefore, it will //not// snow today. Even if the premise It will rain or snow today holds //true//, the conclusion does not necessarily so – it is quite possible that there may be //both//, rain //and// snow, during the same day (or even at the same time). ===== Description ===== In most cases, the underlying error is likely to be a confusion between //inclusive// and //exclusive// [[glossary:disjunction|disjunction]] (see: [[glossary:adjunction|ad­junction]] and [[glossary:contravalence|contra­valence]]). Another possibility is an incorrect application of the [[logic:inferences:modus_tollendo_ponens|Modus tollendo ponens]], especially when mixed with the [[logic:inferences:modus_ponendo_tollens|Modus ponendo tollens]], can also lead to this fallacy. For comparison, the following table compares the two valid forms with the fallacy:
| ^ [[logic:inferences:modus_ponendo_tollens|Modus ponendo tollens]] \\ (valid inference) ^^ [[logic:inferences:modus_tollendo_ponens|Modus tollendo ponens]] \\ (valid inference) ^^ ^ Affirming a disjunct \\ (Formal fallacy) ^^ ^ Premise 1| A ⊻ B \\ (A or B, but not both) || A ∨ B \\ (A or B, or both) || | A ∨ B \\ (A or B, or both) || ^ Premise 2| A | B | ⌐A \\ (not A) | ⌐B \\ (not B) | | A | B | ^ Con­clu­sion| ⌐B \\ (not B) | ⌐A \\ (not A) | B | A | | ⌐B \\ (not B) | ⌐A \\ (not A) |
==== About the name ==== This form is similar to the [[logic:inferences:modus_ponendo_tollens|Modus Ponendo Tollens]], in which one side of an exclusive //disjunct// ([[glossary:contravalence|contravalence]]) is //negated// and it follows that the other is //affirmative//. In this fallacy, the part of the disjunct statement is instead //affirmed// and it is (incorrectly) assumed that the other side must be //negated//. However, the use of the term “disjunction” is somewhat misleading in this context, as this deduction is invalid only for certain kinds of disjunct statements, namely [[glossary:adjunction|adjunctions]] (//inclusive// disjunctions) while it is a valid conclusion for [[glossary:contravalence|contravalent]] (//exclusive// disjunction) statements. ===== When are such inferences valid? ===== //Affirming a disjunct// is a valid conclusion exactly when the premise contains a [[glossary:contravalence|contravalence]] (//exclusive// disjunction) rather than an [[glossary:adjunction|adjunction]] (//inclusive// disjunction). Furthermore, it must be ensured that the set of options is //complete//, i.e., that there are no other possibilities than the ones put forward.
Example: > For dessert, you can have //either// an ice cream //or// a fruit salad. > I’ll have ice cream! > So no fruit salad for you.
By phrasing with "either … or" it is implied that there is an //exclusive// choice to be made: You can choose //either// ice cream //or// fruit salad, //but not both//! (However, the possibility that one might not want any dessert at all is not considered here). If the above premises are fulfilled, this is valid inferrence, namely a [[logic:inferences:modus_ponendo_tollens|Modus Ponendo Tollens]]. ===== See also ===== * [[glossary:disjunction|Disjunction]] * [[logic:inferences:modus_ponendo_tollens|Modus Ponendo Tollens]] * [[logic:formal_fallacies:denying_a_conjunct|Denying a Conjunct]] * [[errors:sherlock_holmes_fallacy|Sherlock-Holmes fallacy]] ===== More Information ===== * [[wp>Affirming a disjunct]] on //Wikipedia// * [[https://www.logicallyfallacious.com/tools/lp/Bo/LogicalFallacies/13/Affirming-a-Disjunct|Affirming a Disjunct]] on //Logically Fallacious// * [[http://www.fallacyfiles.org/afonedis.html|Affirming a Disjunct]] on //Fallacy Files//